Results for 'John V. Tolan'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  11
    Michael Frassetto, Christians and Muslims in the Middle Ages: From Muhammad to Dante. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2020. Pp. xxiii, 287. $95. ISBN: 978-1-4985-7756-4. [REVIEW]John V. Tolan - 2022 - Speculum 97 (4):1194-1195.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  24
    John V. Tolan, Faces of Muhammad: Western Perceptions of the Prophet of Islam from the Middle Ages to Today. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2019. Pp. xii, 309; 17 black-and-white figures. $29.95. ISBN: 978-0-6911-6706-0. [REVIEW]Nabil Matar - 2021 - Speculum 96 (2):570-572.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  64
    Images.John V. Kulvicki - 2013 - New York: Routledge.
    The nature of representation is a central topic in philosophy. This is the first book to connect problems with understanding representational artifacts, like pictures, diagrams, and inscriptions, to the philosophies of science, mind, and art. Can images be a source of knowledge? Are images merely conventional signs, like words? What is the relationship between the observer and the observed? In this clear and stimulating introduction to the problem John V. Kulvicki explores these questions and more. He discusses: the nature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  4. Purpose in nature.John V. Canfield - 1966 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall.
  5.  32
    Possibility or necessity? On Robert Watt’s “Bergson on number”.John V. Garner & Christopher P. Noble - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (1):207-217.
    This paper seeks to highlight the importance of spatial cognition in Bergson’s Données immédiates by engaging with Robert Watt’s reconstruction of Bergson’s argument that every idea of number involves the idea of space. We focus on the second stage of Watt’s reconstruction, where Bergson argues that only space can provide the distinction required for our counting of otherwise identical items. Watt bases his reconstruction on a premise regarding the possibility that identical objects, in the absence of spatial distinction, might remain (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  35
    Modeling the Meanings of Pictures: Depiction and the Philosophy of Language.John V. Kulvicki - 2020 - Oxford University Press.
    John Kulvicki explores the many ways in which pictures can be meaningful, taking inspiration from the philosophy of language. Pictures are important parts of communicative acts. They express a variety of thoughts, and they are also representations. Kulvicki shows how the meanings of pictures let us put them to a wide range of communicative uses.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  7. Student evaluations: The ratings game.John V. Adams - 1997 - Inquiry (ERIC) 1 (2):10-16.
  8.  68
    Moore and Wittgenstein on Certainty.John V. Canfield - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (2):281.
    I can’t help but like a book that calls Wittgenstein the greatest philosopher since Kant and then proceeds to show how On Certainty, a manifestly brilliant but understudied book, sheds light on matters under current debate. It is pleasant to see a highly skilled contemporary put texts from the later philosophy under close scrutiny and mine them for insight, and that outside the bounds of familiar Wittgenstein scholarship.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  9.  15
    Working Knowledges Before and After circa 1800.John V. Pickstone - 2007 - Isis 98 (3):489-516.
    ABSTRACT Historians of science, inasmuch as they are concerned with knowledges and practices rather than institutions, have tended of late to focus on case studies of common processes such as experiment and publication. In so doing, they tend to treat science as a single category, with various local instantiations. Or, alternatively, they relate cases to their specific local contexts. In neither approach do the cases or their contexts build easily into broader histories, reconstructing changing knowledge practices across time and space. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  10.  19
    No calculation necessary: Accessing magnitude through decimals and fractions.John V. Binzak & Edward M. Hubbard - 2020 - Cognition 199 (C):104219.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. The community view.John V. Canfield - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):469-488.
    Saul Kripke, among others, reads Wittgenstein’s private-language argument as an inference from the idea of rule following: The concept of a private language is inconsistent, because using language entails following rules, and following rules entails being a member of a community. Kripke expresses the key exegetical claim underlying that reading as follows.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  12. Self-deception.John V. Canfield & Don F. Gustavson - 1962 - Analysis 23 (December):32-36.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  13.  12
    Becoming human: the development of language, self, and self-consciousness.John V. Canfield - 2007 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This book is a philosophical examination of the main stages in our journey from hominid to human. It deals with the nature and origin of language, the self, self-consciousness, and the religious ideal of a return to Eden. It approaches these topics through a philosophical anthropology derived from the later writings of Wittgenstein. The result is an account of our place in nature consistent with both a hard-headed empiricism and a this-worldy but religiously significant mysticism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14.  45
    Museological Science? The Place of the Analytical/Comparative in Nineteenth-century Science, Technology and Medicine.John V. Pickstone - 1994 - History of Science 32 (2):111-138.
  15.  14
    Creative Discovery.John V. Garner - 2020 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (2):299-321.
    In his commentary on Euclid, Proclus develops what he takes to be an important Platonic critique of the epistemology of abstraction. As I argue, his argument closely reflects terminology and concepts from Plato’s Philebus. Both emphasize the priority—in reality and in our awareness—of the precise over the imprecise. Specifically, Proclus’s famous notion of the psychical “projection” of intermediate mathematical entities, while having no technically exact precedent in Plato, finds a conceptual neighbor in the Philebus’s suggestion that philosophical arithmeticians “posit” pure (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  35
    Bureaucracy, Liberalism and the Body in Post-Revolutionary France: Bichat's Physiology and the Paris School of Medicine.John V. Pickstone - 1981 - History of Science 19 (2):115-142.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  17.  34
    Criteria and rules of language.John V. Canfield - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (1):70-87.
  18.  34
    The Community View.John V. Canfield - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):469-488.
    Saul Kripke, among others, reads Wittgenstein’s private-language argument as an inference from the idea of rule following: The concept of a private language is inconsistent, because using language entails following rules, and following rules entails being a member of a community. Kripke expresses the key exegetical claim underlying that reading as follows.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19.  16
    Past and present knowledges in the practice of the history of science.John V. Pickstone - 1995 - History of Science 33 (100):203-224.
  20.  27
    The Emerging Good in Plato's Philebus.John V. Garner - 2017 - Evanston, IL, USA: Northwestern University Press.
    This study examines Plato's dialogue on the good life and argues, most centrally, that the "pleasures of learning" exemplify, for Socrates, the possibility of good becoming or change.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  48
    Gadamer and the Lessons of Arithmetic in Plato’s Hippias Major.John V. Garner - 2017 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy 9 (1):105-136.
    In the 'Hippias Major' Socrates uses a counter-example to oppose Hippias‘s view that parts and wholes always have a "continuous" nature. Socrates argues, for example, that even-numbered groups might be made of parts with the opposite character, i.e. odd. As Gadamer has shown, Socrates often uses such examples as a model for understanding language and definitions: numbers and definitions both draw disparate elements into a sum-whole differing from the parts. In this paper I follow Gadamer‘s suggestion that we should focus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  52
    Wittgenstein and Zen.John V. Canfield - 1975 - Philosophy 50 (194):383-408.
    Wittgenstein's later philosophy and the doctrines of Mahayana Buddhism integral to Zen coincide in a fundamental aspect: for Wittgenstein language has, one might say, a mystical base; and this base is exactly the Buddhist ideal of acting with a mind empty of thought. My aim is to establish and explore this phenomenon. The result should be both a deeper understanding of Wittgenstein and the removal of a philosophical objection to Zen that has troubled some people.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  30
    John Stuart Mill, John Herschel, and the 'Probability of Causes'.John V. Strong - 1978 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978:31-41.
    While historians of scientific method have recently called attention to the views of many of John Stuart Mill's contemporaries on the relation between probability and inductive inference, little if any note has been taken of Mill's own vigorous attack on the received "Laplacean" interpretation of probability in the first edition of the System of Logic. This paper examines the place of Mill's critique, both in the overall framework of his philosophy, and in the tradition of assessing the so-called "probability (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. The compatibility of free will and determinism.John V. Canfield - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (July):352-368.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  25.  50
    Progressions in mathematical models of international conflict.John V. Gillespie & Dina A. Zinnes - 1975 - Synthese 31 (2):289 - 321.
  26. Paradoxes of self-deception.John V. Canfield & Patrick Mcnally - 1960 - Analysis 21 (June):140-144.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  27.  44
    Natural Histories, Analyses and Experimentation: Three Afterwards.John V. Pickstone - 2011 - History of Science 49 (3):349-374.
  28.  87
    Wittgenstein and Zen.John V. Canfield - 1975 - Philosophy 50 (194):383 - 408.
  29. Giorgio Agamben: The signature of all things: on method, Luca D’Isanto with Kevin Attell : Zone Books, 2009, 124 pp, ISBN: 1890951986 , US $ 24.95.John V. Garner - 2010 - Continental Philosophy Review 43 (4):579-588.
  30.  32
    John Hick's theocentrism: Revolutionary or implicitly exclusivist?John V. Apczynski - 1992 - Modern Theology 8 (1):39-52.
  31.  22
    The Philosophy of Wittgenstein.John V. Canfield (ed.) - 1986 - New York: Garland.
    1. The early philosophy--language as picture -- 2. Logic and ontology -- 3. "My world and its value" -- 4. The later philosophy--views and reviews -- 5. Method and essense -- 6. Meaning -- 7. Criteria -- 8. Knowing, naming, certainty, and idealism -- 9. The private language argument -- 10. Logical necessity and rules -- 11. Philosophy of mathematics -- 12. Persons -- 13. Psychology and conceptual relativity -- 14. Aesthetics, ethics, and religion -- 15. Elective affinities.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  55
    Tractatus objects.John V. Canfield - 1976 - Philosophia 6 (1):81-99.
  33.  17
    Wittgenstein and Buddhism.John V. Canfield - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (1):140.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34. Wittgenstein, language and World.John V. Canfield - 1981 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 90 (1):130-132.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  27
    How might we map the cultural fields of science? Politics and organisms in restoration France.John V. Pickstone - 1999 - History of Science 37 (117):347-364.
  36.  9
    Castoriadis's Ontology: Being and Creation, by Suzi Adams.John V. Garner - 2012 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 43 (3):339-341.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  9
    Castoriadis's Ontology: Being and Creation, by Suzi Adams.John V. Garner - 2013 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 44 (2):225-227.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  8
    Thinking Beyond Identity.John V. Garner - 2017 - Idealistic Studies 47 (1-2):99-122.
    In his Euclid commentary, Proclus states that mathematical objects have a status in between Platonic forms and sensible things. Proclus uses geometrical examples liberally to illustrate his theory but says little about arithmetic. However, by examining Proclus’s scattered statements on number and the traditional sources that influenced him (esp. the Philebus), I argue that he maintains an analogy between geometry and arithmetic such that the arithmetical thinker projects a “field of units” to serve as the bearers of number forms. I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  21
    Thinking Beyond Identity.John V. Garner - 2017 - Idealistic Studies 47 (1):99-122.
    In his Euclid commentary, Proclus states that mathematical objects have a status in between Platonic forms and sensible things. Proclus uses geometrical examples liberally to illustrate his theory but says little about arithmetic. However, by examining Proclus’s scattered statements on number and the traditional sources that influenced him, I argue that he maintains an analogy between geometry and arithmetic such that the arithmetical thinker projects a “field of units” to serve as the bearers of number forms. I argue that this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  8
    Where Is the Voice of the Man the Child Will Become?John V. Geisheker - 2010 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 21 (1):86-88.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  32
    A Brief Introduction to Ways of Knowing and Ways of Working.John V. Pickstone - 2011 - History of Science 49 (3):235-245.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  64
    The Mother of Philip V of Macedon.John V. A. Fine - 1934 - Classical Quarterly 28 (02):99-.
    In 1924 W. W. Tarn published an article in which he attempted to prove that the mother of Philip V of Macedon was the Epirot princess Phthia. Previously all historians had accepted the statement of Eusebius that Philip was the son of Demetrius II and Chryseis, whom, after the death of her husband, the Macedonians gave in marriage to Antigonus Doson. Despite the cogency of Tarn's arguments, his theory has been rejected by both Beloch and Dinsmoor, who adhere to the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  4
    Payment Theory and the Last Mile Problem.John V. Jacobi - 2020 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 48 (3):474-479.
    Health reform debate understandably focuses on large system design. We should not omit attention to the “last mile” problem of physician payment theory. Achieving fundamental goals of integrative, patient-centered primary care depends on thoughtful financial support. This commentary describes the nature and importance of innovative primary care payment programs.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  10
    Peirce’s Philosophy of Science: Critical Studies in His Theory of Induction and Scientific Method.John V. Strong - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (4):655-657.
  45.  20
    Teleological Explanations.Teleology.John V. Canfield, Larry Wright & Andrew Woodfield - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (2):284.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  37
    The discovery of meaning through scientific and religious forms of indwelling.John V. Apczynski - 2005 - Zygon 40 (1):77-88.
    . Because of similarities between some implications of Michael Polanyi's theory of personal knowledge and intelligent design, claims have been made that his theory provides support to the project of intelligent design. This essay contends that, when Polanyi's reflections on a Ideological framework for contextualizing evolutionary biology are properly understood as a heuristic vision, his position contrasts sharply with the empirical claims made on behalf of intelligent design.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  47
    Dysfunctional counterfactual thinking: When simulating alternatives to reality impedes experiential learning.John V. Petrocelli, Catherine E. Seta & John J. Seta - 2013 - Thinking and Reasoning 19 (2):205 - 230.
    Using a multiple-trial stock market decision paradigm, the possibility that counterfactual thinking can be dysfunctional for learning and performance by distorting the processing of outcome information was examined. Correlational (Study 1) and experimental (Study 2) evidence suggested that counterfactuals are associated with a decrease in experiential learning. When counterfactuals were made salient, participants displayed significantly poorer performance compared to their counterparts for whom counterfactuals were relatively less salient. A counterfactual salience ? need for cognition (NFC) interaction qualified these findings. High (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  66
    Wittgenstein, language and world.John V. Canfield - 1981 - Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.
    Language Games 2 This chapter provides some background necessary for subsequent discussions by sketching in the idea of a language game, thereby giving a ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Are Religion and Science Distinct or Dichotomous Realms?John V. Apczynski - 1987 - Tradition and Discovery 15 (1):4-14.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. "A Model" Tractatus "Language".John V. Canfield - 1972 - Philosophical Forum 4 (2):199.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000